this post was submitted on 08 Jan 2025
59 points (100.0% liked)

theory

653 readers
79 users here now

A community for in-depth discussion of books, posts that are better suited for !literature@www.hexbear.net will be removed.

The hexbear rules against sectarian posts or comments will be strictly enforced here.

founded 2 years ago
MODERATORS
 

Hop in, comrades, we are reading Capital Volumes I-III this year, and we will every year until Communism is achieved. (Volume IV, often published under the title Theories of Surplus Value, will not be included, but comrades are welcome to set up other bookclubs.) This works out to about 6½ pages a day for a year, 46 pages a week.

I'll post the readings at the start of each week and @mention anybody interested. Let me know if you want to be added or removed.

31 members! Excited to see this taking off, and proud of us for making it thus far. We have now read ¹⁄₁₈ of Volume I. The first three weeks are the densest, onwards it's smooth sailing and only needs about 20 minutes a day. We're gonna make it, comrades!

Week 2, Jan 8-14, we are reading Volume 1, Chapter 2 & Chapter 3 Sections 1 & 2.

Discuss the week's reading in the comments.

Use any translation/edition you like. Marxists.org has the Moore and Aveling translation in various file formats including epub and PDF: https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/

Ben Fowkes translation, PDF: https://libgen.is/book/index.php?md5=AA342398FDEC44DFA0E732357783FD48

(Unsure about the quality of the Reitter translation, I'd love to see some input on it as it's the newest one)

AernaLingus says: I noticed that the linked copy of the Fowkes translation doesn't have bookmarks, so I took the liberty of adding them myself. You can either download my version with the bookmarks added or if you're a bit paranoid (can't blame ya) and don't mind some light command line work you can use the same simple script that I did with my formatted plaintext bookmarks to take the PDF from libgen and add the bookmarks yourself. Also, please let me know if you spot any errors with the bookmarks so I can fix them!


Resources

(These are not expected reading, these are here to help you if you so choose)


2024 Archived Discussions

If you want to dig back into older discussions, this is an excellent way to do so.

Archives: Week 1Week 2Week 3Week 4Week 5Week 6Week 7Week 8Week 9Week 10Week 11Week 12Week 13Week 14Week 15Week 16Week 17Week 18Week 19Week 20Week 21Week 22Week 23Week 24Week 25Week 26Week 27Week 28Week 29Week 30Week 31Week 32Week 33Week 34Week 35Week 36Week 37Week 38Week 39Week 40Week 41Week 42Week 43Week 44Week 45Week 46Week 47Week 48Week 49Week 50Week 51Week 52


2025 Archived Discussions

Just joining us? You can use the archives below to help you reading up to where the group is. There is another reading group on a different schedule at https://lemmygrad.ml/c/genzhou (federated at !genzhou@lemmygrad.ml ) (Note: Seems to be on hiatus for now) which may fit your schedule better. The idea is for the bookclub to repeat annually, so there's always next year.

Week 1

top 41 comments
sorted by: hot top controversial new old
[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 3 points 13 hours ago* (last edited 13 hours ago) (6 children)

Here are some comments and notes I have on Chapter 2. I'm tryin this Zettelkasten system of note-taking (does anyone have experience with this, is it worthwhile or just a fad?), so I have taken many smaller comments while I've read, and later tried to sort them into "atomic notes" that are geared toward a specific idea or topic. So here are some ideas I got from chapter 2

[Edit: My earlier notes appear last as I posted them first. While each note should be somewhat independent, it may be better to read them from bottom to top?]


Private Property and Commodities

For products to come into relation with each as commodities their “guardians” must bring them into exchange. This requires a recognition of each other's commodity as their private property. Jumping ahead of the chapter for a bit, Marx again states that for exchange to occur each person must treat the other as the commodity’s private owners, and “as persons who are independent of each other. But this relationship of reciprocal isolation and foreignness does not exist for the members of a primitive community of natural origin… The exchange of commodities begins where communities have their boundaries” (pg. 182). The external exchange of commodities has an impact on the internal life of the community. And as exchange becomes more common, some products within the community must be produced for exchange. Exchange repeats, increases, becomes a normal social process, and exchange ratios become dependent on the their production.

There is also a mention that nomadic peoples are the first to develop commodities as their mode of life a.) brings them into connection with other peoples, and b.) already has them in the social habit of alienating their products. I'd like to hear other's thoughts on this, given what we know now about anthropology. I'm thinking of Graeber's Debt.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 2 points 13 hours ago

Comments on Value from David Harvey

Some comments that Harvey makes about value in his A Companion to Marx’s Capital, these comments can be found around pages 35-38

  • Value is historically specific to the capitalist mode of production

  • Value is objective, but immaterial. You can’t directly measure it, it exists in relations between commodities and it needs a means of representation to be expressed. It only only gets expressed in the money form. Measuring value directly in a commodity is like trying to “find gravity in a stone.”

  • It isn’t as if value “exists out there” to be finally expressed as money. Instead, both exchange relations and the value structure dialectically depend on each other and create each other.

I am still thinking about Harvey’s comments on the measurability of value. I have some thoughts, which are in no way fleshed out enough to write out about the possibility of measuring value. Essentially, I’m thinking of this along the lines of computation theory and what it may have to say about “computation” occurring in the real world by real systems.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 1 points 13 hours ago

One Last Question About Money and MMT

There’s one last thing I’d like to tie-in with other articles I’ve read, as well as ask readers here. There was a dig at Proudhon in the footnotes and it reminded me of Michael Robert's critique of MMT? The Modern Monetary Trick

Marx mentions that money “crystallizes out of the process of exchange”. Money comes out of commodity exchange and footnote (4) critiques the “craftiness of petit-bourgoise socialism, which wants to perpetuate the production of commodities while simultaneously abolishing the ‘antagonism between money and commodities’.

This reminds me of Michael Robert’s critique of MMT theory, posted above, where he says that MMT “separates money from value, and … fails to recognize the reality of social relations under capitalism…”

A more in-depth quote form the article

MMT differs from Marx’s theory of money in saying that money is not tied to any law of value that drags it into place like “gravity”; instead, it has the freedom to expand and indeed change value itself. Money is the primary causal force on value, not vice versa!

This echoes the ideas of French socialist Pierre Proudhon in the 1840s. He argued that what was wrong with capitalism was the monetary system itself, not the exploitation of labour and the capitalist mode of production. Here is what Marx had to say about Proudhon’s view in his chapter on money in the Grundrisse: “can the existing relations of production and the relations of distribution which correspond to them be revolutionised by a change in the instrument of circulation?” For Marx, “the doctrine that proposes tricks of circulation as a way of, on the one hand, avoiding the violent character of these social changes and on the other, of making these changes appear not to be a presupposition but gradual result of these transformations in circulation” would be a fundamental error and misunderstanding of the reality of capitalism.

In other words, separating money from value, and indeed making money the primary force for change in capitalism, fails to recognise the reality of social relations under capitalism and production for profit. Without a theory of value, MMTers enter a fictitious economic world — one where the state can issue debt and have it converted into credits on the state account by a central bank at will and with no limit or repercussions in the real world of productive capital.

Now I know that MMT is very popular among leftists and our friends in the News Mega. So I may be opening a huge can of worms, but this appeared very interesting and I’d love to hear ideas on Robert’s criticisms if anyone is familiar with them. I am still absorbing it, so I have nothing to add. When reading Marx’s passage about money, I immediately think about how it compares and contrasts to Graeber’s work on debt. So any ideas would help in my understanding.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 1 points 13 hours ago* (last edited 6 hours ago)

Money Value, Real Abstraction

More on the thought of money and value, and value being this “real abstraction”. I noted a passage toward the end of the chapter where Marx talks about the requirements a commodity must have in order to function as the universal equivalent. What I thought was interesting is that a money commodity must have similar properties to value in order for money to make the real abstraction. For a commodity to function as the form of appearance of value, it must have a homogenous and uniform quality just like abstract labor.

Only a material whose every sample possesses the same uniform quality can be an adequate form of appearance of value, that is a material embodiment of abstract and therefore equal human labor.

And, just like how the only difference between magnitudes of value is quantitative, not qualitative, money must also be “purely quantitative differentiation… divisible at will, and … possible to assemble it again.” (pg 184)

There is also a discussion where Marx says that the fact that money can be replaced by symbols gives rise to a mistaken notion that money itself is just a symbol.. While at some level, it is true that every commodity is a symbol “since, as value, it is only the material shell of the human labor expended on it”, we must not go too far with this idea else we may err and say that the “social characteristics assumed by material objects” are arbitrary products of human reflection. This, to me, reiterates that money and value represent a real social relation. We can’t say that it is purely a product of human imagination. It has an “objective” reality of sorts by the fact that it is not purely subjective or a product of our thoughts or will. It is a real abstraction, an objective feature of commodity exchange, and is determined by the labor-time required for production of the commodity.

A comment by Shaikh in the article I mentioned above about this abstraction.

It is important to stress here that the abstraction process described above is a real social process. Abstract labor is the property acquired by human labor when it is directed towards the production of commodities, and as such, it exists only in commodity production. The concept of abstract labor is not a mental generalization that we somehow choose to make, but rather the reflection in the thought of a real social property. This in term means that abstract labor, and hence value too, are real.” “Neo-Richardian Economic, A Wealth of Algebra, A Poverty of Theory” pg. 70.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 1 points 13 hours ago* (last edited 6 hours ago)

Importance of Money in Making Value Real

Continuing in the vein that @quarrk@hexbear.net was discussing much earlier, it appears there are sections where Marx a points out the importance of money (and hence of exchange) in “making” value. Concrete exchange/money must happen to "complete" the earlier abstraction of abstract value as the source of value. Correct me, here, if I'm misinterpreting what you said earlier.

To the owner of a commodity, every other commodity counts as the particular equivalent of his own commodity… there is in fact no commodity acting as universal equivalent, and the commodities possess no general relative form of value under which they can be equated as values… They can only bring their commodities into relation as values, and therefore as commodities, by bringing them into an opposing relation with some other commodity … the universal equivalent. (pg 180)

And later on page 182-183 (of the Penguin edition)

Commercial intercourse… never takes place unless different kinds of commodities… are exchanged for, and equated as values with, one single further kind of commodity.

This further kind of commodity, is the universal or social equivalent. Which is money, or the money-form.


A question for you nerds: What does Marx mean by money vs the money-form, or value vs the value-form?

From Soviet political economy (Kozlov, and other similar textbooks), they provide the following:

“The social labor embodied in a commodity appears as value,” while “the expression of the value of a commodity by equating it to another commodity is called the form of value.”

And this is where Marx’s earlier discussion (in Chapter 1) gets into the various forms of value: (a) The Accidental Form which contains the relative and equivalent form, (b) The Expanded or Total Form, (c) The General Form, and (d) The Money Form.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 1 points 13 hours ago

The Importance of Exchange, and Use-Values, in Realizing Value, and the Contradiction between Private and Social Labor

In exchange, sellers see no direct use-value in their commodity, else they wouldn’t want to sell it. For sellers, it is the exchange-value of the commodity they hold that matters.

All commodities are non-use-values for their owners, and use-values for their non-owners.

I’m not entirely certain if what follows fits for this chapter, but I’d like to mention some thoughts about the importance of exchange in realizing value, and in the contradiction between private labor and social labor.

Exchange “completes” the loop in recognizing, or not recognizing, private labor as social labor. It is only if the commodity is successfully exchanged, and hence if the commodity has use-value that is socially recognized, that it can be realized as value. Only exchange can prove that the private individual labor was social and counts as abstract labor creating value.

For the labor expended on them only counts in so far as it is expended in a form which is useful for others. However, only the act of exchange can prove whether that labor is useful for others…

My Penguin version of Capital has an introduction written by Ernst Mandel. I thought I’d share his words on importance of use-value in realizing value, and exchange in realizing private labor as social labor:

"... in a society based upon private property and private labor (in which economic decision making is fragmented between thousands of independent firms and millions of independent 'economic agents') social labor cannot immediately be recognized as such... If Mr. Jones has his workers produce 100,000 pairs of shoes a year he knows that people need shoes and buy them... But he has no way to knowing whether the specific 100,000 pairs of shoes he owns will find specific customers... Only after selling his shoes and receiving their equivalent can he say... 'my workers have truly spent socially necessary labor in my factory'. If part of the produced shoes remain unsold, or if they are sold at a loss or at a profit significantly less than the average, this means that part of the labor spend on their production has not been recognized by society as socially necessary labor, has in fact been wasted labor from the point of view of society as a whole... its production has created no value. "

A similar description is given in the Soviet political economy textbook Political Economy: Capitalism - Kozlov (Ed) (1977).

In commodity production based on private property there is a deep internal contradiction between private and social labor. Private ownership … gives [commodity producers’] labor a private character. … At the same time, the social division of labor makes all commodity producers closely interdependent, makes the labor of each of them a part of the aggregate social labor…

While the commodity producer is occupied in making a commodity, the social character of his labour remains unobserved and hidden, but it becomes clear as soon as the products come onto the market. There it is discovered whether or not the labor of a given commodity producer is needed by society and whether or not it will receive social recognition. If the commodity does not find a buyer, that means that the given private labor has not been recognized as part of social labour… (pg 71-72)

Anwar Shaikh also gives his interpretation of exchange “exposing and resolving” the contradictions within production in his paper “Neo-Ricardian Economics: A Wealth of Algebra, a Poverty of Theory”. This starts moving beyond the contents of Chapter 2.

... Marx points to the fundamental contradiction which exists here. On the one hand, each labor process is privately undertaken as if it is independent of all others, with exchange for profit as the goal. On the other hand, this undertaking assumes in advance that other similar labor process will also be there at the right time… Buyers of this product, sellers of the means of production … if it is to be repeated (reproduced).

Each apparently private and independent labor must therefore presuppose a social division of labor.

It is in exchange that the apparent independence of each private labor process collides with the true interdependence inherent in a social division of labor. Exchange is the sphere, as Marx puts it, where the contradictions of commodity production are “both exposed and resolved”.... Exchange is the sphere which the contradiction internal to production itself, the contraction between private labor and the social division of labor, is made visible.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 1 points 13 hours ago

Bearers of Economic Relations

As individuals, buyers and sellers become bearers, carriers, Träger of larger economic relations. Harvey, in his A Compansion to Marx’s Capital (pg. 49-50) takes time to point this out, as does Marx himself in his “Preface to the First Edition” of Capital where he states “individuals are dealt with here only insofar as they the personifications of economic categories, the bearers of particular class-relations and interests.” Individuals come into play in Marx’s political economy in terms of the economic roles they play, and the relation between these roles: buyers and sellers, debtors and creditors, capitalists and workers.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 2 points 13 hours ago

I don't have any notes for Chapter 3 that I feel are complete, so hopefully I don't fall behind.

But, for anyone still reading or struggle with Chapter 3 I'd like to share some encouraging words from David Harvey. This is his last paragraph of his chapter on Money from this Companion, and I return to it when I'm feeling bogged down about what Marx has to say about money.

One final point. This chapter on money is rich, complicated and hard to absorb on first reading. For this reason, as I began by remarking, many people give up on Capital by chapter 3. I hope you have found enough that is intriguing to stay with it. But you will also be glad to know that you do not have to understand everything in the chapter in order to move on. Much of what is said here is more relevant to later volumes than to the rest of Volume I. Armed with some basic, but essential, propositions from this chapter, it is possible to grasp the rest of the material without too much difficulty. From here on in, the argument becomes much easier.

[–] blackbread@lemmygrad.ml 4 points 15 hours ago (1 children)

It's helpful reading others notes, as it helps me focus in on things I may have missed.

I found chapter 2 harder than chapter 1 (even though it's much shorter) because the focus seems more diffuse. It starts by looking at commodity owners, before going into the money commodity.

I found the part about commodity owners especially interesting. The presence of commodities shapes human behavior:

  • Humans with commodities view other humans as commodities. (So my take: a commodity owner doesn't see charity cases, doesn't see immorality; They just see somebody to trade with. That at least is what the exchange process encourages and is different from more direct collaboration or trade where you probably care much more about such details).
  • When you have commodity owners, they effectively "vouch" for each others ownership in the trade; Regardless of what the law says. So the idea of commodity ownership is more fundamental than human laws and is "enforced" by mutual recognition between commodity owners.
  • Commodities want to be exchanged; This is an anthropomorphism, but the idea is if someone is calling something a commodity, it's because they don't want it. So, in a way, commodity owners become chaperones for their commodities.

Marx also mentioned a "rebound effect" where external commodities (for example a nation trading for gas) creates an internal commodities market as people become used to the idea of the externally provided commodity being part of their local economy. I imagine it's true, but wonder if it's as consistent as some of his other statements. A planned economy can probably avoid this -- and small economies probably can avoid this behavior also.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 2 points 10 hours ago

I noted that "rebound effect" when I read it as well. I related it to what I've read about cybernetics and complexity science as an examples of Ashby's Law, and I recently shared some notes about cybernetics in a discussion @yogthos@lemmygrad.ml and I were having about complex systems.

It's possible this is a stretch and these are my quack pet-theories, so be forwarned, but I see parallels with what Marx said to Ashby's Law of Variety in cybernetics. If viewed from this perspective, it is as if that once a community (system) becomes exposed to commodity exchange (from an environment), it is confronted with a system of higher "complexity" or "variety", and this forces an adaptation (or "extinction") of the previous non-commodity modes. Commodity exchange is able to encode more information and can increase the scale and efficiency of the production of use-values by having a "rebound effect" on the communities division of labor. That isn't meant to be a moral judgement, though. Commodity exchange isn't "good" or "better" than the pre-commodity systems, but commodity exchange allows for an increase in information encoding, and so societies that adopt to it are then able to further reproduce. This is how I interpret Marx when he says that exchange bursts local bonds and expands more and more.

Now, this may sound like some Hayekian market triumphalism ("only the Holy Market can encode all economic information, kneel before my prices!"), but Ashby's Law would be no stranger to cyberneticians like Stafford Beer who worked on Project Cybersyn and tried to build these planned economies. Someone like Beer may just respond that once we are able to design a planned economy that can "outcompete" the market, then planned economies will be that which rebounds and bursts through their local bonds. Quantity transforming to quality.

[–] quarrk@hexbear.net 3 points 17 hours ago (1 children)

How are people getting on with the reading?

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 3 points 16 hours ago

I'm enjoying it so far! One thing that has helped me actually engage more with the material is the input from readers like you that get me to think more critically.

[–] StillNoLeftLeft@hexbear.net 9 points 4 days ago (2 children)

I've decided to make notes from my reading so I can return to it later. Might have the spoons and time to do this every week, might not.

I have uploaded my notes from this week as a pdf to a file sharing site in case they might be useful for others. You can download the file from here.

It includes my comments in cursive and the bullet points are this weeks reading condensed to what I felt to be key points. I have bolded bits that I found to be especially important.

[–] StillNoLeftLeft@hexbear.net 9 points 4 days ago* (last edited 4 days ago)

Adding that while reading these first chapters and especially the parts about money the Marx quote that has been playing in my head over and over is this one:

"Political economy, this science of wealth, is therefore simultaneously the science of renunciation, of want, of saving and it actually reaches the point where it spares man the need of either fresh air or physical exercise. This science of marvellous industry is simultaneously the science of asceticism, and its true ideal is the ascetic but extortionate miser and the ascetic but productive slave. Its moral ideal is the worker who takes part of his wages to the savings-bank, and it has even found ready-made a servile art which embodies this pet idea: it has been presented, bathed in sentimentality, on the stage. Thus political economy – despite its worldly and voluptuous appearance – is a true moral science, the most moral of all the sciences. Self-renunciation, the renunciation of life and of all human needs, is its principal thesis. The less you eat, drink and buy books; the less you go to the theatre, the dance hall, the public house; the less you think, love, theorise, sing, paint, fence, etc., the more you save – the greater becomes your treasure which neither moths nor rust will devour – your capital. The less you are, the less you express your own life, the more you have, i.e., the greater is your alienated life, the greater is the store of your estranged being. Everything which the political economist takes from you in life and in humanity, he replaces for you in money and in wealth; and all the things which you cannot do, your money can do. It can eat and, drink, go to the dance hall and the theatre; it can travel, it can appropriate art, learning, the treasures of the past, political power – all this it can appropriate for you – it can buy all this: it is true endowment. Yet being all this, it wants to do nothing but create itself, buy itself; for everything else is after all its servant, and when I have the master I have the servant and do not need his servant. All passions and all activity must therefore be submerged in avarice."

source

The first chapters fully explain to me how it is possible for money to take this position. How having money becomes a representation of things instead of a thing and how this can justify the act of sitting on it. It's becomes what it can do (like credit) and not what it does. It never has to enter circulation to embody all commodities and when you own money, you in theory own all the commodities that symbol could buy for you, that you could exchance it for.

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 4 points 4 days ago

That's a great idea, thanks for sharing!

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 15 points 5 days ago* (last edited 1 day ago) (2 children)
[–] khizuo@hexbear.net 4 points 5 days ago (1 children)

Aaah can't believe I missed the start! Please add me

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 4 points 5 days ago

No problem! We started a few days late due to not knowing who was going to do the posting, so you're not alone! Welcome!

[–] quarrk@hexbear.net 6 points 5 days ago (1 children)

With Genesis out of the way, I am ready to ascend to the ethereal and fertile realm of super-socialism!

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 7 points 5 days ago (2 children)

Marx's humor is underrated, dude is goofy lol

[–] devils_dust@hexbear.net 6 points 5 days ago (2 children)

I love the footnotes on my edition for this, grandpa could've made a whole side career out of making fun of the bourgeoisie

[–] BeamBrain@hexbear.net 4 points 5 days ago (2 children)

This also applies to Lenin

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 4 points 4 days ago

Lenin always bringing up Kautsky and shitting on him throughout his writing never ceases to make me laugh out loud

[–] devils_dust@hexbear.net 3 points 4 days ago

True! I remember marking down this passage as a "I'll definitely use this irl when needed" (emphasis mine):

Certain bourgeois writers [...] have expressed the opinion that international cartels, being one of the most striking expressions of the internationalisation of capital, give the hope of peace among nations under capitalism. Theoretically, this opinion is absolutely absurd, while in practice it is sophistry and a dishonest defence of the worst opportunism.

https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1916/imp-hsc/ch05.htm

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 4 points 5 days ago

What a goofy grandpa marx-joker

[–] IceWallowCum@hexbear.net 4 points 5 days ago (1 children)

This was a genuine surprise the first time I tried to read Kapital

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 3 points 5 days ago

Yea, it shines through in his shorter texts too but he has more room to stretch his comedic muscles in Capital I feel.

[–] quarrk@hexbear.net 8 points 5 days ago* (last edited 5 days ago) (1 children)

Posting an excerpt from Theories of Surplus Value that may help clarify an important aspect of chapter one, namely, the absolutely essential role played by money in making value a general category that transcends the accidental exchange of two commodities.

TSV (my bold added)

[T]he product as value must be the embodiment of social labour and, as such, be directly convertible from one use-value into all others. […] Thus the labour of individuals has to be directly represented as its opposite, social labour; this transformed labour is, as its immediate opposite, abstract, general labour, which is therefore represented in a general equivalent, only by its alienation does individual labour manifest itself as its opposite.  The commodity, however, must have this general expression before it is alienated.  This necessity to express individual labour as general labour is equivalent to the necessity of expressing a commodity as money.  The commodity receives this expression insofar as the money serves as a measure and expresses the value of the commodity in its priceIt is only through sale, through its real transformation into money, that the commodity acquires its adequate expression as exchange-value.  The first transformation is merely a theoretical process, the second is a real one.

Thus, in considering the existence of the commodity as money, it is not only necessary to emphasise that in money commodities acquire a definite measure of their value—since all commodities express their value in the use-value of the same commodity—but that they all become manifestations of social, abstract, general labour; and as such they all possess the same form, they all appear as the direct incarnation of social labour and as such they all act as social labour, that is to say, they can be directly exchanged for all other commodities in proportion to the size of their value; whereas in the hands of the people whose commodities have been transformed into money, they exist not as exchange-value in the form of a particular use-value, but as use-value (gold, for example) which merely represents exchange-value.  A commodity may be sold either below or above its value.  This is purely a matter of the magnitude of its valueBut whenever a commodity is sold, transformed into money, its exchange-value acquires an independent existence, separate from its use-value.  The commodity now exists only as a certain quantity of social labour-time, and it proves that it is such by being directly exchangeable for any commodity whatsoever and convertible (in proportion to its magnitude) into any use-value whatsoever.  This point must not be overlooked in relation to money any more than the formal transformation undergone by the labour a commodity contains as its element of value.  But an examination of money—of that absolute exchangeability which the commodity possesses as money, of its absolute effectiveness as exchange-value which has nothing to do with the magnitude of value—shows that it is not quantitatively, but qualitatively determined and that as a result of the very process through which the commodity itself passes, its exchange-value becomes independent, and is really represented as a separate aspect alongside its use-value as it is already nominally in its price.

It seems, in Capital chapter one, that Marx argues all his conclusions follow directly from the analysis of two commodities in exchange, x commodity A = y commodity B. Then, it seems, that in order to prove the concept of value, he asks the reader to suppose mentally that although A traded for B in one instance, it could have traded for C or any other commodity. This mental exercise is not sufficient to prove the general, universal character of this third thing, value.

What proves in actuality the general, universal character of a particular concrete labor is the fact that it exchanges for the money commodity, the universal equivalent. Without money, the qualitative equality of one concrete labor with all other concrete labors is only ideal. Money makes this an actual fact by itself embodying abstract universal labor. More can be said on this point but it starts to creep outside the scope of chapter one.

Again referencing the same Rubin lecture I posted elsewhere in this thread, he explains the above, starting with a couple quotes from Marx:

Rubin/Marx

“Within the value-relation and the value expression included in it, the abstractly general accounts not as a property of the concrete, sensibly real; but on the contrary the sensibly-concrete counts as the mere form of appearance or definite form of realisation of the abstractly general ... This inversion, by which the sensibly-concrete counts only as the form of appearance of the abstractly general and not, on the contrary, the abstractly general as property of the concrete, characterises the expression of value. At the same time, it makes understanding it difficult.” (The Value Form, p.39-140).

At another point Marx says:

“It is as if together with and besides lions, tigers, hares and all the other real animals, which as a group form the various genuses, species, subspecies, families etc of the animal kingdom, there also existed the Animal, the individual incarnation of the whole animal kingdom.” (Kapital 1st ed. p.234).

To decipher this statement by Marx, we must say that in commodity production the abstract universal really appears not as characteristic or attribute of the concrete, the sensuous-real (i.e. of the concrete modes of labour), since in order to abstract the specific universal features from these concrete modes of labour, it would need a unified organ, which does not exist in commodity production. The concrete kinds of labour are therefore not assimilated one with another through abstraction of some universal characteristics, but through comparison and equation of each of these kinds with a particular determined concrete kind which serves as phenomenal form of universal labour. In order that concrete labour becomes universal, universal labour must appear in the form of concrete labour […]

Using Marx’s abstract Animal analogy, it’s as if a concrete animal (such as a living zebra) were proven to be a particular form of Animal, not by mental abstraction by a human, but by the zebra’s actual conversion into Animal. Commodities prove their value content only by being sold for the money commodity. As Rubin says, echoing Marx: “Each,” (referring to commodities and money), “is in reality what the other is ideally, and ideally what the other is in reality.”

Side note, it seems the last sentence in that excerpt could have religious implication too: ”In order that concrete labour becomes universal, universal labour must appear in the form of concrete labour.” This brings to mind Christianity, in which God as the abstract human has to emerge in a concrete human form, in order to redeem humanity as Godlike. Pretty sure Marx actually says this in some other writing.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 6 points 3 days ago (2 children)

I really appreciate your comments, and I like the idea that is by the concrete formation of money in exchange, that the abstraction of value becomes real (if I'm understanding that correctly).

I don't know if this is a term Marx uses, or if I got it from Harvey, or etc., but I like to think of it as a real abstraction. As in, the actual real act of exchanging of commodities through money is what is doing the abstraction. Abstract labor is a real abstraction because Capitalism makes this abstraction. Value becomes a real abstraction because of the concrete nature of exchange.

Perhaps I have some misunderstanding of myself, though.


What you have been writing reminds me of an article I've read by Ian Wright. I'd like to share it, and get your or other's opinions on it.

Ian Wright - What is Abstract Labour and Who Does the Abstracting

The article is about seeing Capitalism as a control system which controls, regulates, and does the abstracting through feedback loops. He later compares capital to an egregore, which is a fun analogy (and why the blog is called Dark Marxism in the first place).

The abstraction is not ours because our cognition is not performing the abstraction. We are not the abstractor. Instead, the mysterious abstractor is taking the measurements about labour time and connecting the form of value, which is money, to its content, which is abstract labour.

The details get more into what Capitalism is as a system, and we aren't at that point yet in Marx's work. Capital is what creates exchange value, and is what makes abstract labor. If already familiar with capitalism, then the description is not new, but the recontextualization of thinking of it as a control system, or even an egregore is still illuminating.

Wright starts by sharing your concern

that Marx’s argument — for the proposition that the special common property shared by all commodities is labour — is unsatisfactory.

While your solution is to go forward with finding how money concretely makes this abstraction in exchange, Wright takes a similar approach but also goes beyond exchange and talks about capital's profit maximization as the abstractor which makes abstract labor a real abstraction.

So capital controls concrete labour, the real labouring activities of the working population in all their diverse manifestations. And capital controls actual labour-time... It is capital itself that holds a metaphorical stopwatch in its hand, measuring and accounting, and judging and condemning...

And the goal of capital is to convert concrete labour into abstract labour, into the kind of labour that both fits into the division of labour, so it can be exchanged against other labour ... in order to yield profits for the capitalist firm...

In other words, “abstract labour” is manifested, brought into reality, by capital itself. Maximising profit is identically the process of maximising the manifestation of abstract labour out of concrete labour.

[–] quarrk@hexbear.net 4 points 1 day ago* (last edited 1 day ago) (1 children)

Adding on to my previous comment, there is a well-known refutation of the model used by Ian Steedman which Ian Wright invokes in his category-mistake paper. Andrew Kliman and Ted McGlone published this refutation in their paper on the temporal single-system interpretation (TSSI). You can see that Equation 2 in Wright's paper, his definition of standard labor values, is the same as Equation 3 in the TSSI paper. So, the refutation is quite directly targeted at the interpretation used by Wright, which he uses to justify his modification of Marx's theory.

Fun fact, the partner of Radhika Desai — frequent contributor to Geopolitical Economy Report on YouTube — is Alan Freeman. Freeman is an associate of Kliman and has also long argued in defense of the TSSI.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 4 points 1 day ago (1 children)

Hey no worries! I enjoy these comments, they get me thinking. Especially because while I am aware of TSSI, I haven't studied it in depth as much as I have Wright's work. I consider myself still learning off of this, so taking time to give Kliman's work more thought is just a continuation of my own learning. I will admit, that I have some gut feeling that the labor theory of value should, and can, be a quantitative theory which also can explain value and price formation. And maybe it turns out I'm completely wrong, but I'll just keep reading and learning and seeing where it leads. In fact, this is something that excites me about this reading group. I'd like to go through Capital with others here with these debates in mind. My own understanding of Ian Wright's work also comes from Shaikh's interpretation of how the Transformation Problem is to be interpreted in his paper "Neo-Ricardian Economics: A Wealth of Algebra, A Poverty of Theory" (its title continuing the Marxist trend of being snarky and sarcastic lol). In it, he does criticize neo-Ricardians dismissal of value and the LTV, and he argues that the correlation between surplus value and profit is preserved if one considers not just the circuit of capital, but also the circuit of revenue - considering the surplus value that is consumed by capitalists when they purchase consumption items. Shaikh also reiterates this argument in his lectures for his book Capitalism: Competition, Conflict, Crises. This is essentially (as I see it) what Wright's capitalist consumption matrix C is measuring in his "super-integrated labor-values." Of course, the difference in our understanding sounds like it comes down to how quantitative vs qualitative Marx's theory of value should be, and whether the entire input-output framework is the right way to approach this.

I definitely get what you mean, though, by writers which tend to "modernize" Marx. I often get a bad taste in my mouth by them too, and usually some alarm bells go off. Given that, I think my STEM-bias though makes me inclined to think that the LTV can be quantitative, though, and that "the numbers should work out". And Wright's explanations make sense to me given that mindset. But, like I said, I need to give TSSI a fair investigation too. It's just sometimes not fun going through years of (often harsh) debates back and forth between the various interpretations of Capital.

This is fun, though. And, like I said, I'm excited to keep these debates in mind as we continue reading!

I'll give more thoughts as they come to me. And feel free to share your writings on Marx's value theory being more valuable as a qualitative theory.

[–] quarrk@hexbear.net 3 points 1 day ago (1 children)

rosa-salute thanks for your message Sebrof. I’m going to bed now. I don’t have much to say, except that I totally agree that there is a quantitative side to Capital that has to work out numerically. And it does, with a correct interpretation (the qualitative aspect). For example, labor is the content of value, but only a particular kind of labor. The theoretical work required to understand the kind of labor, and as what commodities are compared, is the tofu and potatoes of the book.

[–] Sebrof@hexbear.net 2 points 15 hours ago

Thanks for your responses, I really appreciate them rat-salute . I don't have more to add at this point either. I'm sure there'll be more to discuss as we continue reading, and as I read the TSSI papers as well. I'm looking forward to it!

[–] quarrk@hexbear.net 4 points 2 days ago

About five years ago, I read Ian Wright's paper about the "category mistake" in Marx, so I'm familiar with him. I also read the article you shared here, thank you.

Wright is not the first to use the term real abstraction. I believe it was first used by Alfred Sohn-Rethel of the Frankfurt School. Sohn-Rethel's work is intriguing — I have had his book Intellectual and Manual Labour in my to-read list after reading the introduction a few years ago. I am not knowledgeable enough about the precise usage of the term real abstraction to have an opinion on its validity as used by the Critical Theorists. Doubtless, Marx believed that abstractions (such as value) have a real, material presence in the world. This kind of abstraction does not exist merely in the mind, because in fact the abstract concepts are a reflection of material reality. Furthermore, it would not be possible to simply "think away" abstractions such as money without changing the basis for those abstractions.

I'm not quite sure where to place Wright. Is he a Sraffian? a neo-Ricardian? a "Critical Theorist"? It seems like he takes inspiration from each of these, but belongs to none. In any case, like those schools, much of Wright's effort is focused on correcting mistakes which he alleges Marx made, in order to "modernize" the Marxian theory or settle old debates. This honestly rubs me the wrong way and I have a hard time reading Wright for that reason.

I basically agree with the introductory third of Wright's article about abstract labor. He loses me when he says that capital is the "abstractor". The stuff about control also seems quite out of left-field, not motivated by anything inherent in the subject matter, but an assertion that he hopes will click with the reader. It would resonate with a certain STEM-minded person (such as myself), especially given his other work which is heavy on linear algebra. But it kinda falls flat for me. In his attempt to clarify Marx, he ends up more confusing.

As for Wright's linear algebra-based approach to Marx's theory of value, I think he has made an error due to misunderstanding the qualitative aspect of Marx's theory of value, which Marx emphasizes in several places as the most important advance over Ricardo and classical political economy. Wright, like Ricardo and neo-Ricardians (e.g. Sraffa) conceive of value almost purely quantitatively. The problem with modeling Marx's theory of value in terms of input-output models is that it conceives of value in terms of technical labor inputs; i.e., the value of a product is the sum of its concrete labor inputs. I can explain more if needed but I think it's clear that this is a serious departure from Marx, barely recognizable as Marxist and more properly termed Ricardian in my opinion. Marx was not interested in a quantitative theory of price formation. His focus was on a qualitative theory of value, because he recognized Ricardo's incomplete conception of value as what stalled Ricardo's progress.

I'm sorry if this isn't the response you were going for. I actually appreciate discussing Wright's ideas because spending 2-3 weeks pondering his paper, and ultimately rejecting it, helped me very much in clarifying my own understanding of Marx. I also don't mind if you disagree with what I wrote here. Thanks again for the reply and also I appreciate your input to these threads as well!

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 9 points 5 days ago

As a side note, I know many are still finishing Chapter 1. That's okay, we started a few days late. However, if we catch up now, we will maintain pace to finish Volumes 1-3 in a single year, so I encourage trying to push through these denser first few chapters so we can maintain a smooth roll.

[–] Vampire@hexbear.net 8 points 5 days ago (1 children)

Thank you for doing this. I really didn't want to for another year, I don't expect to be spending as much time on Hexbear this year as last.

As a small note, you missed Week 52 of the archive.

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 4 points 5 days ago (1 children)

No problem! I might drift away a bit eventually but I at least wanted to read Capital in a group setting.

And thanks for the bit on Week 52, I'll get that fixed.

[–] Vampire@hexbear.net 3 points 3 days ago (1 children)

Don't forget to unpin the previous week each time. 'Unfeature in Community'

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 2 points 3 days ago

Okay, will do! Thanks!

[–] glimmer_twin@hexbear.net 4 points 5 days ago (1 children)

Ayyy can I sign up please! I’ll catch up hehe

[–] Cowbee@hexbear.net 3 points 5 days ago

Absolutely, welcome!